09 August 2025

The human psyche (temporalogically)

 Psyche according to Aristotle

What is the human psyche? The modern empirical science of psychology does not confront itself with this question, but contents itself with a quick definition such as consciousness or cognition and, more recently, with the dogma that these latter are somehow generated by material, neurological brain processes.

For deeper questioning of the human psyche, we have to return to Aristotle's De Anima (On the Soul), if only because his investigation laid the groundwork, i.e. the foundational concepts and way of thinking, that has governed Western (and today global) thinking on the psyche, even, unknowingly, on modern psychology.

After reviewing and criticizing the thinking of his predecessors in Book I, Aristotle starts anew to pursue the question, "what the psyche is" (τί ἐστιν ψυχὴ 412a3), a question that cannot be answered without understanding fundamental concepts from Aristotle's Metaphysics. Here I will have to assume a knowledge of these concepts. His investigation proceeds in a number of steps to find the psyche of "physical bodies" (σώματα...φυσικά 412a12f) that "have life" (ἔχει ζωήν 412a13), and is thus wider than the question concerning the specifically human psyche with which I am concerned here. Living bodies for Aristotle comprise plants, animals and humans as a special kind of animal.

The first answer deems the psyche "to be an essence as the 'look' of a physical body having the potential/ability to live" (οὐδίαν εἶναι ὡς εἴδος σώματος φυσικοῦ δυνάμει ζωήν ἔχοντος 412a20f), whereby this eidetic 'look' is the body's "having its end" (ἐντελέχεια 412a10) or "perfected presence" as living. (A non-living thing such as an axe, for example, has the eidetic look and perfected presence of something that is good for chopping.) This perfected presence of the psyche accounts for a living physical body's both "sleeping and waking" (ὔπνος καὶ ἐγρήγορσις 412a25). The "ability to live" is then specified as having organs (ὄργανα 412b1) which is exemplified by a plant (a living physical body) having roots in analogy to the stomach (412b4) that enables nutrition.

The general definition of the psyche is then given as the "essence/whatness of such a body" (τὸ τί ἦν εἶναι τῷ τοιῳδὶ σώματι 412b11) with organs, which amounts to "having the starting-point/principle of movement and standstill/rest within itself" (ἔχοντος ἀρχὴν κινήσεως καὶ στάσεως ἐν ἑαθτῷ 412b17). This concept of psyche applies to the living physical body as a whole and also to its parts. Aristotle provides the example of the eye as a bodily organ, whose essential whatness as organ of a living body is its "eyesight" (ὄψις 412b19), i.e. its ability to perceive visually. The eye is endowed with such psyche even when it is closed and cannot see, just as a living body is still alive even when asleep, i.e. 'dead to the world'. The organ of sight in this case is an organ of sense perception (αἴσθησις) that enables an openness to and receptiveness for everything presently visible in the world. Such sense perception is necessary for a living physical body in order for it to orient itself and move itself in its environs, and the bodily organ of the eye enables such self-movement characterizing for Aristotle what life itself is, and the role of the psyche as the essence or whatness that enables life, in this case, the sense perception necessary for life.

Temporalogical conception of the human psyche

What does this entail for the attempt to conceive specifically the human psyche starting from the elementary concept of three-dimensional time? The conception of life in this case is restricted to that of human life. The psyche is conceived first of all as belonging to the openness of three-dimensional time composed of its three characteristic dimensions of past, present and future familiar to us humans, but also mostly taken for granted and overlooked because, as such, these temporal dimensions are empty. We humans are instead focused on what comes from each these dimensions: from the past, from the present and from the future, and not on the empty, unmoving dimensions themselves that hide themselves in their inconspicuousness. 

What moves or stands still in coming from any of the three temporal dimensions is received by the human psyche which has this temporal receptiveness by virtue of belonging to the openness of three-dimensional time which thus provides the initial conception of the human psyche itself. Openness to the environs through sense perception is at the basis of the traditional conception of life in general*, and human life in particular, entails that this openness is restricted to what sense perception can perceive in the present. By contrast, a temporalogical account of the human psyche, and thus of human life itself, starts with its openness to all three temporal dimensions and what comes from each of these dimensions into the psyche's focus in order to be understood. This implies that the human psyche has a faculty of understanding that interprets what comes into focus in one way or another. It is thus hermeneutic through and through. This psychic faculty of interpretive understanding may be called the mind which is able to roam throughout three-dimensional time.

Hence e.g., to expect the visit of a friend from the temporal dimension of the future, is already to understand, to interpret the friend as a living human, which in turn implies already an implicit understanding both of what life is and of what, or who, a human essentially is, i.e. of a human's whatness or whoness. For Aristotle and Plato and the entire Western tradition, the human is a kind of animal, a legacy by which today's thinking remains bound, or rather, a legacy in which it remains incarcerated for the sake of preventing any deeper questioning and recasting. Even though the metaphysical, ontological interpretation of human being has receded into oblivion since the rise of empiricist positivism in the mid-19th century, and today's hegemonic understanding of the human as an evolutionarily evolved animal with an exceptionally large and complicated brain holds sway, there is still the need to pose the question of who the human is, thus revising this traditional understanding that has become thoughtless dogma. This requires 'doing a da capo' and starting again from an alternative beginning that may be called temporalogical, rather than ontological.

The phenomenon of human life itself, interpreted temporalogically, starts from the psyche's belonging to three-dimensional time. The self-movement of human life is then initially conceived, i.e. interpreted hermeneutically, as the ability of the psyche's understanding to roam, perhaps apparently haphazardly, throughout the openness of three-dimensional time by virtue of the psyche's power of imagination, focusing on this or that which comes to mind from any of the three temporal dimensions. This kind of self-movement of human life may be appropriately called the life of the mind. Mental movement thus gains precedence over physical movement upon which Western thinking remains fixated to the present day.

A friend's coming to visit is then tacitly 'always already' (a priori) interpreted as a human endowed with a psychic openness to three-dimensional time and a mind able to roam freely through this temporal openness. This has consequences for how an encounter between friends is to be understood, namely, as an interplay between two humans, each of whom is endowed with an understanding mind endowed with free, temporally three-dimensional movement. To unfold further the phenomenon of interplay neglected by traditional thinking, however, cannot be undertaken in this brief post, whose aim has been to merely indicate how Aristotle's metaphysical-ontological conception of life can be recast temporalogically from an alternative starting-point. I have attempted this recasting, at least in outline, in On Human Temporality.

* Cf. "..the living being characterized first of all by sense perception", ...τὸ δὲ ζῷον διὰ τὴν αἴσθησιν πρώτος 413b3, the first sense treated being that of touch (ἁφή 413b5).

Further reading: Aristotle De Anima (On the Soul) esp. Book II Chap. i 412a1-413a10.

On Human Temporality: Recasting Whoness Da Capo De Gruyter, Berlin 2024.

02 August 2025

27 July 2025

Quest for truth or will to power?

Philosophy is often characterized as the quest for truth, a noble striving. Truth itself is usually said to be located in the λόγος (logos), i.e. in statements, propositions that can be true or false. Plato's famous struggle against the Sophist in his eponymous dialogue strives to catch the slippery Sophist, who claims that it is impossible to make a false statement because that would amount to saying and asserting what is not, μὴ ὅν (mae on), non-being. The great predecessor, Parmenides, had been interpreted as prohibiting any attempt to say μὴ ὅν because it amounts to saying nothing. The Sophist, however, always said something, and accordingly this could not be contested because a false statement was impossible to make. His statements were all true.

The upshot of Plato's famous, intricate dialectic in his Sophist dialogue (254b-257a) among the five generic ideas (γένη) of movement (κίνησις, kinaesis), standstill (στάσις , stasis), same (αὐτό , auto), other (ἑτερον , heteron) and being (ὅν, on) is that non-being (μὴ ὅν) is indeed possible, because the idea (εἴδος, eidos) of other is able to mix with that of being. The negation of being through otherness does not result in total annihilation of being, but rather in a determinate negation. E.g. the negation of beauty (τὸ καλόν) is not nothing but the non-beautiful (μὴ καλόν, mae kalon), the ugly.

With respect to the logos (λόγος) as being (ὅν), it is shown through the dialectic that the logos can be either true (ἀληθής) or false (ψεῦδος), the latter through mixing with otherness. The Sophist is thus unmasked as a purveyor of falsehoods, and correspondingly, the Philosopher is shown to be the one who seeks the truth through true statements and enters the battle to refute false, sophistical ones. 

Does that mean that the philosopher is like an investigative journalist who uncovers the true facts of the matter by exposing false statements? Not so fast. There is a difference between true, i.e. correct, facts as stated by a logos, and the truth of phenomena themselves, as we shall see.

The philosophical quest for truth would seem to have nothing to do with a struggle for power over others, for truth itself is supposed to be pure, standing above and untainted by the falsity that is employed to fool and mislead others. Philosophy would then be the endeavour calling upon us to humbly submit to the unvarnished truth as revealed by true statements. In particular, such true statements can be deduced syllogistically, i.e. by drawing conclusions from accepted premises via rules of inference. Logical argument then consists in presenting such a cogent derivation from accepted premises, that the opponent has to bow to the superiority of the incontestable argument. Hence there is an element of striving for power, after all, albeit a benign one, for the so-called good of the other, when all falsity is expunged from argument as far as possilble. Indeed, today's (analytic) philosophy is often represented as the contest among various positions to present the better, irrefutable argument.

A statement, however, always says something by interpreting what it is talking about as such-and-such. E.g. I hear a noise above my head and interpret it as a pigeon scratching around on the roof, an interpretation that may turn out to be either factually correct or false on closer inspection. I also implicitly interpret the pigeon, without further ado, as a living being, and in this interpretation there is further a implicit interpretation (or preconception) of what life itself is. The 'as' here is the hermeneutic or interpretive as, that is not merely factual, but concerns the preconceptions that inundate our understanding of the world and without which we would not be able to lead our daily lives.

What is the case, then, when I see swifts wheeling about overhead? I implicitly interpret them as a kind of bird flying in the sky, and flying itself is a kind of movement, so the generic idea of κίνησις (kinaesis) comes into play here. I easily recognize and understand the phenomenon of movement, albeit implicitly. My implicit interpretive understanding of what movement is has to be unfolded to become explicit. This interpretation is not singularly my own, but borrowed from the long tradition of interpretations of movement going back to the Greeks. The explicit interpretation of what seems to be self-evident has been the proper business of philosophy from the start.

Why the Greeks? Because it is the Greek philosophical interpretations of movement that tacitly have become globally hegemonic today by providing the foundations for all the modern Western sciences. The question, What is movement?, motivated Greek thinking from the very beginning. Early on, in Timaios, Plato counterposes the kind of movement called γένεσις (becoming)  to ἀεί ὅν (eternity, standstill). Movement for the Greeks comprises especially all kinds of physical change, starting with becoming. The early philosophers were therefore also called 'physiologists' (φυσιολόγοι). Even time itself is conceived (hermeneutically) as either a measure of change or as the element in which all change takes place, whereas standstill, changelessness are identified with timelessness, as still is the case today. In this way, the phenomenon of time was interpreted as derivative of physical movement.

Although the Greeks are familiar with other kinds of change, such as a change of heart or soul, i.e. of the ψυχή, their thinking focuses on physical changes. Not only are the various kinds of physical movement (change of place, quantitative change, qualitative alteration, progeneration) investigated, but such movements are conceived as having a cause (αἴτιος). Scientific knowledge (ἐπιστήμη) for the Greeks is always connected to aetiology. In this interest there resides already a will to power over (all kinds of physical) movement, and phenomena of movement are interpreted already under the impetus of this will to power. Efficient causality amounts to knowing 'if this, then that'. Such causal rules can be applied to control movement. If-then rules themselves rely upon a linear conception of time as a succession of instants that can be exactly measured by some sort of clock: If at one instant this happens, at the next, that will happen. This enables physical movements of all kinds to be predicted or, even better, manipulated and controlled.

The choice of kinds of physical movement as the focus of attention for Greek thinking on movement derives from its conceiving physical beings themselves to be composed of a 'look' or form (εἴδος) and matter (ὕλη). Matter, namely, can be manipulated. First of all, any know-how for making something, i.e. τέχνη ποιητική (technae poiaetikae), enables the possessor of the know-how, i.e. the maker, to causally control and master the movement of making toward its envisaged end goal, or (τέλος).

It was Aristotle who, in Book Theta of his Metaphysics, provided the first and only ontology of movement we have today, namely, the ontology of efficient-causal, productive movement that surreptitiously pervades all of modern science, even those sciences whose will to power over movement is directed also at non-physical kinds of movement, notably psychology, sociology and economics. Hence e.g. psychopharmacology aims to control psychic movement by means of material medications. 

By trying to fit the ontology of efficient-causal movement to kinds of movement that are patently not physical, such as the phenomenon of rhetorical speaking, Greek thinking already did violence to the phenomenon by misinterpreting it (cf. Aristotle's Art of Rhetoric). Due to this infection by the unbridled will to power over all kinds of movement and change, modern science continues to do more violence to phenomena of movement by interpreting them as reducible to material causes. Hence, in particular and notably, there is a collapse of the mind into the brain in modern scientific thinking, a corollary of which is the denial of free will.

The interpretation of phenomena of movement through an ontology of efficient-causal movement is not false in the sense of being factually incorrect. On that level, given its presuppositions, everything is perfectly correct, and experiments can be carried out to verify the hypotheses postulated! The misinterpretation lies deeper, by forcing an ontological interpretation onto phenomena of movement that do not at all conform to the ontology of efficient-causal movement. The untruth of the interpretation cannot be detected by any empiricist scientific methodology, because the violence to the phenomena in question has already been perpetrated beforehand, a priori, in the very preconception. Hence, for example, data gathered from a large enough sample may reveal statistically significant correlations that point to underlying efficient-causal connections that remain ultimately merely hypothesized. A link between cause and effect is never physically detectable, but only hypothesized on the basis of experience with a postulated theoretical model. But no imaginable experiment can even prove that efficient-causal links pertain universally between occurrences.

The consideration of phenomena of movement and change different from the paradigmatic ones employed to consolidate today's scientific thinking can show that alternative ontologies of movement are necessary. The non-hermeneutic nature of today's hegemonic philosophy as taught in universities, however, prevents it from seeing the will to power nested within the noble quest for truth. This blindness is precisely the way the status quo can be upheld and scientific progress progress whilst simultaneously suppressing any alternative ontologies*.

* Cf. e.g. Social Ontology of Whoness: Rethinking Core Phenomena of Political Philosophy De Gruyter, Berlin 2018, Chapter 5 'Ontology of Exchange'.

Further reading: Plato Sophist.

Martin Heidegger Platon:Sophistes Gesamtausgabe Band 19 (GA19) Marburger Vorlesung Winter Semester 1924/25 ed. Ingeborg Schüßler, Klostermann, Frankfurt §§77-81.

Philosophy as quest for truth.

Arguing positions — or interpreting phenomena?.

10 July 2025

Space in three-dimensional time

Space is a much-used word with many nuances and connotations, the basic meaning presumably being the physical one of where physical things are located, namely, in space. Space's sister concept is 'time'. Time and space go together like horse and carriage and are treated pretty much on a par, but with space having an edge on time. Time tends to be imagined spatially as intervals from then to then along a so-called time-line. One speaks uninhibitedly of 'points of time' and time intervals between them. It seems easier for our Western mind to imagine time geometrically. Geometries themselves are imagined spatially because (Euclidian) geometric figures are abstractions from the usual, experienceable three-dimensional space. From the very beginnings of physics with the Greeks, time was conceived geometrically, counted along a continuous time-line, and places became positions or points in geometrical space.

In modern relativity physics, time is explicitly cast spatially as the path of light in a four-dimensional space-time. When any physical event occurs, is measured by the path of light from the event to the observing subject or apparatus, any physical event in the cosmos being recorded in space-time co-ordinates (x,y,z,ct). 

How does this square with the recast conception of time as three- or even four-dimensional? The tables are turned completely and utterly. The openness of three-dimensional time is entirely pre-spatial, and even space itself is attributed a derivative status. What essences — i.e. what presences and absences in three-dimensional time for the psyche's power of imagination — encompasses far more than the physical, which is endowed first of all with extension, magnitude. Physical entities in traditional ontology are also material. Such physical, material entities with extension require places (τόποι, _topoi_) to be somewhere, and so make room for themselves by taking places. This carries over to temporalogy in which only physical, extended, material essents essencing in time require places. 

All other essents presence and absence in the psyche's all-encompassing openness of three-dimensional time, without requiring places, to be interpreted, and hence understood, in some way by the psyche's understanding. Thus, we mortals belong first of all to this temporal openness as the most primordial, and probably most inconspicuous, phenomenon open to our mind. What comes to mind is mostly non-physical, e.g. an everyday matter that has to be dealt with, such as your tax return or the weekly shopping or your child's overuse of digital media. Although physical things requiring 'wheres' or places are involved in such matters, even then they are generally not even physically present to the senses, but come to mind non-sensuously. They are simply part of a situation or a matter to be taken care of. Countless other issues and essents that come to mind, such as the idea of fairness or value, are in themselves entirely whereless (but may materialize somewhere).

The notion of space itself is derived from imagining physical essents in places, say, in a geographic landscape or in a building, and abstracting from the solid, physical things located therein, to attain (perhaps topographical or survey) maps and (perhaps detailed architectural) plans. Spaces such as the open sky over a valley or the empty space in a room result from subtracting physical essents in their respective places and in this sense are on the way to total abstraction. Such abstractions are a poor substitute for countryside or for what Australian indigenous peoples call 'country'. Once abstraction is performed, physically located things can then, turned around, be conceived geometrically as point masses in a Euclidian or some other geometrical space, and these point masses can then be inserted into dynamic equations of motion (perhaps to become military targets for bombing). The essencing of physical things perceptible by the senses taking their respective places at some 'where' or other, however, is existentially prior to the abstract conception of space itself. Through centuries of habituation, today's conventional Western thinking conceives space abstractly, i.e. more or less geometrically (or even mathematically via Cartesian co-ordinates), as the empty spatial openness that provides positions for connected point masses. Physical things are then conceived as the material concretion of such abstract geometrical figures. This is especially apparent in architectural design, but also, say, in how A.I. deployed in autonomous vehicles detects 'objects'. Geometry itself, however, is a discipline whose figures are abstractions from the experience of the physical world with its places where physical essents take their places.

All-encompassing three-dimensional time that is open to us mortals through the fourth temporal dimension is truly all-encompassing, encompassing even (the idea of) geometrically abstract space itself in which physical, extended essents can be conceived to take their places. First and foremost, or primordially, we essence in time. To the present day, our thinking skips over this inconspicuous, all-encompassing, three-dimensional temporal openness, confusing it with the openness of space which, however, is only derivative, d.h. not an elementary, primordial phenomenon. The wide open spaces of a landscape are themselves temporal, essencing in three-dimensional time for our mental capacity of understanding. Physically extended, temporally essencing essents taking their places generate space, rather than conversely: Space does not make room for physical essents by conceding places to them.

The same goes for the world, which essences primordially in time. Three-dimensional time itself encompasses the world, even the universe, since nothing at all can essence for us, i.e. for our understanding mind, without this temporal openness. Modern physics, however, studies the universe under the rubric of cosmology, whereby it reduces the cosmos to being composed entirely of matter and forces pertaining to matter. Otherwise this science has no purchase on its 'object', that is conceived as independent of us 'subjects' and investigated via apparatuses receiving data (principally electromagnetic radiation) from 'out there'. But if the cosmos essences in three-dimensional time, perhaps there is more to it than lifeless matter, i.e. that pre-material, non-physical, whereless essents inhabit the cosmos which we mortals, caught in the hermeneutic cast of our historical age, cannot yet conceive.

Further reading: Why three-dimensional time?.

The stone is in the psyche.

On Human Temporality: Recasting Whoness Da Capo De Gruyter, Berlin 2024.

Movement and Time in the Cyberworld: Questioning the Digital Cast of Being De Gruyter, Berlin 2019 esp. Chap. 2.

01 July 2025

Why three-dimensional time?

Why three-dimensional time? is a question mostly prefaced by the question, What is three-dimensional time?, simply because the very notion meets with perplexity everywhere and, among the intellectual elite especially, very quickly with dismissal. Why? Because the phenomenon of three-dimensional time is taken as the starting-point in the attempt to go back to scratch — da capo — to revise our Western thinking, to enable our mind to make a fresh start. This upsets well-established ways of thinking, is strenuous and often leads to dead-ends that require steps to be retraced. 

Any attempt to rethink elementary phenomena da capo will meet with massive resistance, because old habits of thought, with all their uninterrogated preconceptions and prejudices, are tied also to deeply entrenched vested interests, starting with preserving one's own status and identity, one's very whoness. 

Taking three-dimensional time as starting-point amounts to claiming that it is the most elementary phenomenon implicitly already invoked when trying to think through any other phenomenon. This claim can only be made good by actually undertaking the attempt to think through how our phenomenal world hangs together precisely through conceptual interconnections among key elementary phenomena, starting with: what is the conceptual relationship between time and movement. Such thinking through (διάνοια) may be called dialectic, a way of thinking, talking-through, discoursing, discussing practised already by Plato with respect to key elementary concepts but, famously, also much later by Hegel, who learned much from Plato's dialectic. Thinking through conceptually the relationship between time and movement reveals that from the start, with Aristotle, Western thinking got this relationship back to front and upside down.

I have already published a book* undertaking the attempt to think through da capo from a concept of (the phenomenon of) three-dimensional time, so there is a danger of merely repeating myself. To avoid that, here only theses are presented that articulate salient aspects of my attempt. Readers are thus left to connect the dots themselves.

i) The phenomenon of three-dimensional time is readily accessible to anyone who takes the trouble to look at it, to ponder it slowly, providing from the outset potentially a radically different way to think about the human psyche and mind that actually has to be spelt out.

ii) The human psyche is conceived as belonging to the openness of three-dimensional time, which provides the initial conception of (mortal, human) life. The psyche's openness to the world is no longer primarily mediated by the bodily senses in the temporal dimension of the present as has traditionally been the case with sense perception (αἴσθησις). Indeed, consideration of the body only comes later along the path of thinking.

iii) The openness of three-dimensional time is for us mortal humans. This entails it must be passed through to us through a fourth temporal dimension to reach us. Hence four-dimensional time! Our mortal liveliness is our psyche's belonging to and partaking of three-dimensional time.

iv) The mind's movement within all-encompassing three-dimensional time already heals the split between subject and object that is the hallmark of thinking in the modern age, for there is no outside to time and hence no 'external' world vis-à-vis an 'internal' world of consciousness, and especially no 'objective' time 'out there' nor any 'inner' time. 

v) Healing the subject/object split amounts to rehabilitating Parmenides' insight that thinking and being belong together (τὸ γὰρ αὐτὸ νοεῖν ἐστίν τε καὶ εἶναι Frag. 3), but putting it on a entirely new foundation, because 'being' now means 'essencing' within the openness of all three temporal dimensions. Now 'minding' and essencing belong together, the mind itself being the psyche's faculty of understanding. 'Beings'  become 'essents' essencing in the openness of three-dimensional time by presencing and absencing for the mind. What has traditionally been investigated as ontology now becomes temporalogy, an investigation of the modes of essencing of essents in three-dimensional time.

vi) Physical movement of material entities loses its privileged position as the paradigmatic kind of movement from which traditional one-dimensional time is counted. Kinds of movement other than the physical, material come into view. Matter no longer serves as a self-evident basis for thinking, as in the modern sciences.

vii) Time is no longer derivative of physical movement, but rather conversely, all the different kinds of movements happen, or 'essence', within the all-encompassing openness of three-dimensional time. Linear time counted off physical movement turned the Western mind and world upside down from the very start.

viii) Traditional ontology implicitly presupposes physical movement as paradigmatic, whence the dominant ontology of physical movement was developed and generalized by sleight of hand in the modern sciences to other kinds of movement. Different kinds of movement other than the physically material require their own ontologies, or rather, temporalogies of essencing essents. These present a challenging task for thinking attempting a fresh start.

ix) The cause-effect link ubiquitously assumed in modern science, that goes along with the one-dimensional time-line, including a cyclical one-dimensional time-line, loses its self-evidence. Movement in three-dimensional time is less constrained, freer, since the three temporal dimensions are independent of each other, but dovetail. In truth, mental movement is the freest kind of movement that cannot be constrained by reducing it to material, physical movement unless we allow our own thinking to be thus constrained. The hegemonic modern scientific way of thinking exercises this restriction and constraint today on our mind.

x) With non-physical kinds of movement coming into view, the concept of matter is relegated to its proper place, and non-material kinds of movement beyond the purview of the modern sciences given their due. On the whole, the psychic-mindful pre-material comes into view.

xi) The hoary mind-body problem can be taken on from a completely different angle, since mind and body are no longer separate, but rather, the body is within time and thus in the mind which, in turn, is conceived as the understanding faculty of the psyche. How body and mind interplay with each other is no longer restricted to the temporal dimension of the present, but attains a further intricacy by paying heed to the other two temporal dimensions.

xii) The psyche is no longer thought as embodied, but rather the body as empsyched and thus as entimed. Empyschment entails that the body is alive precisely through aspiring to partake, via the psyche, of the openness of three-dimensional time. Thus, traditional ways of thinking are turned upside down.

xiii) Phenomena of deconcealment and concealment associated with truth (ἀλήθεια) have to be rethought paying due attention to the three-dimensionality of time, since they no longer occur solely or primarily in the present. A complex intertwining of de/concealment with the three temporal dimensions has to be thought through.

xiv) How we mortals sociate with one another in society is a kind of movement in its own right, different from physical movement, requiring its own temporalogy. The sociating interplay is a one of ongoing mutual estimation, of mutual esteeming, evaluating, appreciating, etc. along with their deficient opposites.

xv) Mortals' economic sociating in an historical kind of economy called capitalism (our own age) also requires its own temporalogy that takes into account both the character of the competitive gainful game, in which we mortals are all players, and the underlying, hidden, sociating Medium of thingifying value endlessly accumulating, i.e. endlessly valorizing. All that essences becomes a fleeting 'look' (form, εἶδος) of thingifying value transforming cyclically through its various 'looks' in order to generate a surplus.

Further reading: On Human Temporality: Recasting Whoness Da Capo* De Gruyter, Berlin 2024.

23 June 2025

Braucht Demokratie Philosophie?

Hier einige Notizen zu einem Gespräch im Kölner Philosophischen Forum am 06. Juni 2025.

Ich greife nur eine Frage auf, nämlich Achims Gegenthese zu Hartmut Rosas 'Demokratie braucht Religion': 'Demokratie braucht Philosophie'. 

Die Demokratie bezeichnet heute — sehr kurz und skizzenhaft gefaßt — eine politische Verfassung (eine geregelte Weise des gesellschaftlichen Miteinanders), wodurch das Volk selbst die Quelle bzw. Arche der über es ausgeübten Macht sein soll, und zwar dadurch, daß die einzelnen Bürger i) ihre Meinungsfreiheit bezüglich der öffentlichen politischen Angelegenheiten ausüben dürfen wie auch ii) ihre Stimme zur Wahl von Abgeordneten in der gesetzgebenden Institution abgeben können. Die Gesetze wiederum werden letztendlich durch Staatsgewalt durchgesetzt und aufrechterhalten. In der demokratischen Politik geht es um einen Streit der vielen Meinungen darüber, wie die überlegene Staatsmacht ausgeübt werden soll — ein durch die Meinungsfreiheit vermittelter Machtkampf der Bürgermeinungen also, in dem sowohl das Eigeninteresse als auch das Gemeinwohl eine Rolle spielt oder spielen sollte. 

In der Philosophie hingegen geht es nicht um Meinungen, sondern um Wahrheit und zuvor schon um die Frage, was überhaupt Wahrheit ist, d.h. die Frage nach dem Wesen der Wahrheit. Bei solchem Fragen wird bereits in Frage gestellt, ob Meinungen wahr sein können, und wenn ja, unter welchen Umständen. Z.B. ist eine Meinung schon wahr, wenn sie richtig ist? Ist eine richtige Meinung wahr, wenn sie begründet werden kann? Ist überhaupt die Wahrheit mit der Richtigkeit von Tatsachen gleichzusetzen? Schon mit solchen Fragen ist ersichtlich, daß die Philosophie vor der Politik mit ihrem Machtkampf der Meinungen liegt. Die Philosophie ist überhaupt vorpolitisch, politische Fragen müssen ausgeklammert bleiben, eben weil wesentliche Fragen vorher geklärt werden müssen, worauf die Politik oder politische Meinungen keine Antworten geben können. Umgekehrt versteht nicht einmal die Politik, ob demokratisch oder nicht , genuin philosophische Fragestellungen. Wenn einer seine 'politische Philosophie' hat, ist zu hinterfragen, ob diese Philosophie auf bloße Meinung und feste Überzeugung hinausläuft oder eher durch ihre Wahrheit eine wohl begründete politische Haltung erst ermöglicht. 

Mitten in Platons berühmtem Werk über die Verfaßtheit der Polis — in seiner Politeia bzw. (lateinisch) Res publica VII 514a2-517a7— finden wir das berühmte Höhlengleichnis, in dem gleichnishaft gesagt wird, worum es in der Philosophie geht, nämlich um eine "Umlenkung der ganzen Seele" (περιαγωγὴ ὅλης τῆς ψυχῆς), und zwar vom gefesselten Blick auf die bloßen Tatsachen zum wahren Blick auf die Idee des Guten (ἰδέα τοῦ ἀγαθοῦ). Das Wort 'Idee' kommt vom Griechischen ἰδεῖν, 'sehen'. Eine Idee ist also ein Anblick, den ein Seiendes von sich aus einem Anblickenden bietet, der ihn so oder so versteht bzw. deutet. Welche Seele ist bei dieser totalen Umdrehung gemeint — die Einzelseele oder die Gesamtseele eines Volks bzw. der gesamten Menschheit? Wenn jene, dann ist die Bemühung um die Philosophie eine Bemühung um die Selbstverwandlung, durch die ich lerne, ganz anders zu sehen bzw. zu verstehen, nämlich die Wahrheit der Ideen selbst, die mit der Richtigkeit der Tatsachen nicht verwechselt werden darf. Ich bin dadurch verwandelt, daß ich die Welt durch ein Gefüge von zusammenhängenden Ideen verstehe. Die Welt selbst ist eine andere geworden, eben weil sie von Grund auf anders ausgelegt wird.

Die Bemühung des Philosophierens, diese Differenz und damit die Ideen selbst sehen zu lernen, bestünde demnach in einer Auseinandersetzung mit sich selbst oder, wie Platon sagt, in einem Dialog der Seele mit sich selbst. Die Idee des Guten als höchster Idee sehen zu lernen, ist nicht die Bemühung, eine Vorstellung davon zu bilden, was gut für mich ist, denn dies wäre eine bloße Meinung, bloß meine gegenüber anderen Meinungen. Die Frage nach der Idee des Guten ist zunächst keine inhaltliche, sondern danach, was Gutsein überhaupt heißt. Dasselbe gilt auch für die Idee der Gerechtigkeit, die der Freiheit, die Idee des Menschen, die des Lebens, die der Bewegung, die Idee des Kapitals usw. 

Solche Einsichten zu erlangen, ist in erster Linie eine Sache der Selbstauseinandersetzung bzw. des Dialogs mit sich selbst in der 1. Person, gleichsam eins zu eins. Ich muß lernen, alle Vor-Urteile, alle Vor-Begriffe, die den Blick auf die Ideen selber verstellen, wegzuräumen. Es geht nicht um bloß individuelle Ideen bzw. Vorstellungen, sondern um die Seinsweisen von Seiendem. Die Anblicke sind gemeinsame, über deren Deutung wir auch miteinander in einem philosophischen Gespräch reden können, in dem es nicht bloß um Wissenserwerb geht, sondern jeweils auch um Selbst-und-Welt-Verwandlung. Die gemeinsamen bzw. allgemeinen Ideen, wovon gesprochen wird, gehen uns als Einzelne an, und es gibt keine Garantie, daß wir in diesem Gespräch zu einer gemeinsamen Ansicht der Sache selbst kommen. 

Nichtsdestoweniger setzen sich in der Geschichte entscheidende Leitideen, wie z.B. die Idee der Gerechtigkeit oder die Idee der Energie, durch. Diese Leitideen sind keine ewigen, unveränderlichen, wie die griechische Philosophie dachte, sondern selbst in einem tiefen Sinn geschichtlich-schicksalhaft.

Ein philosophierender Dialog mit sich selbst oder anderen ist also zu unterscheiden von irgendwelchen Analysen einer faktischen, sachlichen Lage, wie sie z.B. politische Analysten, Soziologen oder Historiker bieten, denn solche können und müssen in der sog. 'objektiven' — etwa auf dokumentierten Fakten basierenden — 3. Person angeboten werden und haben zumeist den narrativen Charakter eines Geschehens. Solche 'Geschichten' können sehr wohl in den demokratischen Medien hin und her diskutiert werden. 

Die Differenz zwischen den Tatsachen und den Ideen kann als ontologische Differenz bezeichnet werden, womit auch der wesentliche Unterschied zwischen den modernen Wissenschaften und der Philosophie bestimmt ist. Denn die Ideen bringen das Sein des Seienden auf den ontologischen Begriff, während die modernen Wissenschaften — diese stillschweigend und ahnungslos voraussetzend — von den festgestellten experimentellen bzw. empirisch-gegebenen, ontischen Daten ausgehen, um ihre theoretischen Modelle zu 'verifizieren' oder ihre empirischen Studien durchzuführen, um festzustellen, wie die Lage zur Zeit faktisch ist. Auch dies sind Bemühungen in der 3. Person, die keine Selbstauseinandersetzung bzw. -verwandlung erfordern. Ich bleibe nach wie vor unverändert, wer ich bin, wenngleich etwas kenntnisreicher. Die Welt bleibt im Grunde dieselbe. Hingegen in der Philosophie mache ich eine Bewegung durch, in der, wer ich bin und wie die Welt in Ganzen verstanden wird, sich wandelt. 

Insofern braucht die Demokratie, wie sie in modernen (noch) liberalen Gesellschaften gelebt und praktiziert wird, keine Philosophie; als solche kann sie damit nichts anfangen. Denn sie geht (und muß gehen) von den Menschen, wie sie sind, und ihrem Dafürhalten aus. Es können höchsten ihre Ansichten in politischen Machtkämpfen — z.B. Wahlkämpfen — durch demokratische Debatten und rhetorische Mittel beeinflußt werden. Die Frage nach der Idee des Menschen, d.h. nach dem, was bzw. wer der Mensch ist, kann in der Demokratie oder gar in den Medien als Orten der freien Meinungsäußerung nicht einmal gestellt werden, sondern ist zuvor schon stillschweigend geschichtlich beantwortet und steht fest. 

In unserem Zeitalter (der Neuzeit) und schon seit langem, d.h. seit dem ersten Anfang mit dem griechischen Denken, ist die Frage nach dem Wesen des Menschen mit einer Was-Antwort beantwortet. Wir sind entworfen und somit geschichtlich-schicksalhaft geworfen als eine Art Tier, d.h. als eine Spezies (um deren Überleben es angeblich evolutionär geht), auch wenn die nach-Cartesische europäische Philosophie noch gern vom 'Bewußtseinssubjekt' redet. Mit unserer materialistisch vorausgesetzten Basis im Tiersein sind wir heute auf dem besten Weg das, was die Philosophie als νοῦς bzw. Geist bezeichnet, auf die neuronale Tätigkeit des Gehirns zu reduzieren. Bereits heute 'denkt' man so von sich. Die Philosophie hat schon längst ausgedient, während die Neurowissenschaft in Begleitung der rasant aufkommenden KI in der immer weiter um sich greifenden Cyberwelt ihren Siegeszug antritt. Trotzdem ruft die Demokratie heute ohnmächtig nach sog. ethischen Maßstäben bzw. 'Leitplanken'. 

Gibt es, gibt Es heute noch die Möglichkeit eines Denkens mit der Kraft, die Frage danach, wer wir als Menschen sind, von einem anderen Anfang aus zu stellen, um damit unser Menschsein geschichtlich anders zu entwerfen? Sind einige von uns in einem Schritt zurück vom festgefahrenen Weltentwurf für ein solches Infragestellen überhaupt empfangsbereit?

Soviel für heute. 

Weitere Lektüre: Platon Politeia VII. Buch.

Harmut Rosa Demokratie braucht Religion Kösel Verlag München 2022.

On Human Temporality: Recasting Whoness Da Capo De Gruyter, Berlin 2024.

11 June 2025

Energy-hungry, surrogate Cyberworld

It seems we have fast adapted to life in the cyberworld, that used to be called cyberspace, a misleading term because the cyberworld is more than a space. This is indicated already by the 'cyber' in its name that derives from Greek κυβερνᾶν (_kybernan_) 'to steer, guide, govern'. The cyberworld has everything to do with governing all sorts of movement via algorithmic control. It is also a world because it is all-encompassing, enabling near-total immersion in it as a surrogate alternative to the familiar physical and social worlds. As a surrogate, it is also dangerous, especially for the youth, by offering an escape from problems in the interplay with others when growing up. It seems you have more control playing algorithmically steered games than interplaying with flesh-and-blood others. The algorithms exercise a mesmerizing attraction especially on young minds through the seemingly endless and easy existential possibilities they offer.

The basic unit of the cyberworld is the Universal Turing Machine, a mathematical construct thought up by Alan Turing in the 1930s to model what he regarded to be human thinking. In his 1936 paper on Computable Numbers, he casts human thinking as computation, a hermeneutic recasting of what has long been conceived as reason (νοῦς _nous_, ratio, rationality), with enormous ramifications that, more often than not, are sold to a naïve and misled public as 'human progress' in 'improving lives'. This ambivalent progress consists in enhancing power over kinds of movement even beyond the 'classic' case of physical movement, especially to the kinds of movement through which we humans sociate with one another. Such enhancement includes increasing immersion in and dependence upon the cyberworld with its media platforms and communication apps, and ever-increasing subjugation to and dependence upon what the algorithms steering the cyberworld allow or disallow.

But what is an algorithm and what does it have to do with the Universal Turing Machine? The 'Universal' refers to Turing's ideal construction that can accept any computable algorithm at all to control it via instructions. Although such an ideal machine will never be built, it nevertheless theorizes what any computer at all does, namely, work step-by-step through the digital data input to the algorithm employing purely if-then rules encoded in the algorithm. Both the algorithm and the data are nothing other than strings of digital bits, 0 and 1, or bit-strings. The algorithmic bit-string steers how the data bit-string is to be acted upon by the algorithm's logical if-then rules to generate step-by-step, along the one-dimensional time-line of successive now-steps, a third bit-string as output. The algorithm is hence a set of encoded if-then instructions. The output bit-string controls some kind of movement either within or outside the cyberworld. The cyberworld thus consists of countless trillions of algorithmic bit-strings copulating with data bit-strings, whose output bit-strings may merely be fed into other algorithms or used directly to control a movement, e.g. whether you can access your online bank account or whether a rocket launches.

Since any computer, even if it be a super-computer or a quantum computer, works according to if-then rules, in principle, any computation can be carried out by a Turing machine with the appropriate algorithm. In turn, any algorithm at all, even those driving multi-level artificial neurons employed in Artificial Intelligence, can be broken down, in principle, into the Turing simplicity of a bit-string. It is also easy to see that, since the Turing machine only computes according to if-then rules, computing already existing data bit-strings, it acts with blind necessity from the past, i.e. it does not 'see' into the temporal dimension of the future at all. Such imaginative seeing into the future, envisaging a possibility, however, is the hallmark of human freedom that a Turing machine cannot simulate.

In truth, a Turing machine is not in time at all. It is only we humans who are exposed to the openness of three-dimensional time and are able, for instance, to insert logical if-then rules into an algorithmic bit-string with a particular end or τέλος (_telos_) in mind. A corollary of this is that the Artificial Intelligence employing multi-level, so-called 'deep-learning', artificial neurons, no matter how mind-bogglingly complex these become, only works by detecting patterns in already existing data and extrapolating them into the future. Predicting what is coming from the future thus becomes a statistical matter relying on the so-called Law of Large Numbers: in the long run, in a significant number of instances, the A.I. algorithm will generate correct predictions. When deployed e.g. as advertising in the cyberworld's mass markets, A.I. will 'predict' consumers' behaviour sufficiently well, based on the personal data collected on their previous consumer behaviour. 'Sufficiently well' here means merely that the advertising will generate enough hits (actual purchases) to be worth the trouble, and especially the cost, of doing the market research, i.e. gathering the personal data of unsuspecting prospective customers, and writing the appropriate A.I. algorithm to nudge their purchasing behaviour.

The cyberworld conceived as countless algorithmic bit-strings copulating with countless input-data bit-strings to generate countless output bit-strings controlling movements of all kinds (physical, mental, social, ...) is, of course, a theoretical idea that nevertheless provides an answer to the ontological question: What is the cyberworld? The idea of the Universal Turing Machine is the key to grasping its essence, its whatness. However, the cyberworld as we know it is actually physically constructed by deploying the suitable technologies from the material sciences through electromagnetic engineering (esp. constructing fast digital networks) to computer programming. Actually carrying out computations in this artificial, engineered world is a kind of physical movement that, in turn, requires physical energy to drive it. To change a bit in a material electromagnetic medium from 0 to 1 or vice versa requires electrical energy that has to be generated in some way. Electrons must be made to move in a controlled way.

This contrasts with the movement of the human mind itself, that can only be crudely modelled by conceiving it as computation or as physical movement at all. The mind moves freely and effortlessly, pre-spatially and pre-materially, through the openness of three-dimensional time, hip-hopping from one temporal dimension to another and understanding what comes into its focus one way or another. The mind is hermeneutic, interpretive in nature, not computational, employing the brain as its organ in an extremely energy-efficient way. Today's A.I. experts and neuroscientists marvel over how energy-efficient the brain is, after having misguidedly conceptually reduced mental movement to physical brain movement, imagining that  consciousness is an immaterial epiphenomenon generated by the physical movement of material neurons. How does the brain manage such energy-efficiency? they ask in their perplexity, imagining themselves to be committed materialists. 

This acknowledgement of perplexing energy-efficiency does not stop them from continuing to physically construct and extend the energy-inefficient, artificial, surrogate cyberworld. That is their mission. In so doing, they notice that the physical energy requirements to perform digital calculations explode exponentially. Already today, data centres, especially those carrying out A.I. computations, are consuming immense amounts of electrical energy surpassing the electricity consumption of entire small cities. The need for algorithmic control of all kinds of movement through the digitized, electromagnetic medium of the cyberworld, however, is insatiable, since it has proved itself to be highly effective. 

The cyberworld has turned out to be invaluable as the medium of choice for algorithmically disseminating disinformation on a mass scale, in particular, to influence voting behaviour in elections. The state has discovered that it is indispensable for controlling the movements of its citizenry, e.g. through surveillance as well as for tax collection. Digital technologies are today indispensable for increasing productivity and accelerating the turnover of deployed capital, thus enhancing the endless valorization of thingified value (The Medium). The cyberworld is also the domain of a global mass market for both capitalist enterprises and consumers where produced goods and services are sold to realize revenues for capitalist enterprises both large and small. The opening-up of the internet for commercial purposes in the 1990s was a boon for endless profit-making, starting with the giant U.S. tech corporations that were the first to see its capitalist potential.

In other posts I have discussed what lies behind this insatiable striving for power over movement of all kinds that dovetails so seamlessly with the striving for endless valorization. These are two ambivalent 'devilishly divine' ideas that have possessed our mortal mind and are personified by two hitherto unknown gods (or demons) whom I have named Willy P. and Pleon Exia. The cyberworld represents perhaps the consummate realization of the two gods' collaboration.

Further reading: 'Turing's cyberworld of timelessly copulating bit-strings' 2012.

'Turing's Cyberworld' in Information Cultures in the Digital Age: A Festschrift in Honour of Rafael Capurro Matthew Kelly & Jared Bielby (eds.) Springer VS, Wiesbaden 2016 pp. 65-81.

'Algorithmic Control of Movement in Time: Abolishing even our selves ourselves' in Kinder und Jugendliche in der Krise: Gegenwärtige Herausforderungen und neue Perspektiven Rainer J. Kaus, Hartmut Günther (eds.), transcript Verlag, Bielefeld 2025 pp. 219-233.

Movement and Time in the Cyberworld: Questioning the Digital Cast of Being De Gruyter, Berlin 2019.

On Human Temporality: Recasting Whoness Da Capo De Gruyter, Berlin 2024. 

Tale of the Qua: A Philosophical Comedy KDP 2024.

The Good & other gods.

31 May 2025

The Good & other gods

It is general knowledge to those conversant with philosophy that the highest idea in Plato's thinking is called the Good, τἀγαθόν (_t'agathon_). The corresponding highest idea or εἶδος (_eidos_ 'sight', 'look') in Aristotle's Metaphysics, which he names "the god"(ὁ θεός), is the Fair, τὁ καλόν (_to kalon_). The two words are very often used synonymously in ancient Greek, and even combined into one word: καλοκἀγαθός (_kalokagathos_, 'fair and good'), the 'fair and good', the 'excellent'. 'Fair', καλόν, can be taken in the sense of 'beautiful', but also in the senses of 'noble', 'excellent', 'useful', 'fair in dealings', 'justly good', just as ἀγαθόν, can. 

Beings in their being, i.e. in their partaking of being conceived as presencing, offer to mortals the sight of their goodness and fairness in the multiple senses noted. Insofar as beings are deficient, lacking goodness and fairness, they offer instead the sight of their badness, ugliness, unfairness. For Aristotle, the highest, divine 'sight' of the fair is the "unmoving mover" that motivates movement toward the end or τέλος (_telos_) of fairness. The bad or τὁ κακόν (_to kakon_), as the lack of the good and fair, detracts from this end, drawing all into an opposite movement.

In Aristotle's thinking, along with the εἶδος or sight, the end or τέλος is still conceived as a motivating cause of movement. In the modern sciences, both eidetic and teleological causes of movement have been eliminated in favour of the two remaining Aristotelean causes: the efficient and the material. It must be noted, however, that in evolution theory and biology, the teleological cause of movement and change is implicitly present and ubiquitously deployed. How so? Because all life strives to live; evolution theorists as well as biologists invariably talk and think in terms of how mutations and certain features of organisms enhance their chances of survival. The telos of the living is life itself.

Be that as it may, the (remaining) efficient cause is the scientific know-how itself that knows how to efficiently move and manipulate the material cause, which is physical matter in one or other of its 'sights'. The core modern science of mathematized physics focuses intensely on matter as putatively the ultimate cause of all, and the modern mind seems to be more or less entirely taken in by these hubristic scientific pretensions. "We are stardust" (Joni Mitchell), sings one popular song.

Plato's and Aristotle's idealistic gods have been pushed aside and pooh-poohed by modern science in favour of what is called a scientific worldview of objective reality that, in turn, boils down to what the empiricist scientific method wrings out of empirical, material facts as 'verifiable'. Modern science is said to be (objectively) evidenced-based, whereas all other thinking is regarded as tinged more or less by (subjective) ideology. Such secular thinking is apparently godless, without any connection to the divine. For this reason, even in this secular age (at least in the West), modern scientists often seek compensation and solace in religious belief. Religions have an afterlife even after having suffered the onslaught of the materialist scientific worldview that crystallized in the 17th century and triumphed (apparently once and for all?) in the latter half of the 19th century. Even philosophy capitulated, adapting for survival as an ancillary. After the rise of empiricist positivism in the mid-19th century, the analytic philosophy that emerged at the turn of the 20th century achieved its apogee of self-denial and surrender to positive, i.e. fact-based, modern science in the guise of logical positivism, from which it has scarcely recovered. Nonetheless, this impoverished philosophy maintains its hegemony among the philosophies via the corrupted political and economic hegemony of the Anglo-American world.

Which brings us back to ideas as gods. Are there ideas that reign surreptitiously as gods in these apparently godless times whilst remaining unseen as such? This is a paradoxical thought, because the essence of an idea or εἶδος is to be seen as a sight by the mortal mind. Perhaps these ideas have just been overlooked or shoved aside and repressed by our shared mind that is and has been preoccupied by two related, apparently eminently secular ideas for centuries, or even millennia, namely, i) the idea of progress in effective human knowledge and ii) the idea of the betterment of the material conditions of human life known today as the 'standard of living'. The two ideas are easily linked in what can be called materialist ideology by pointing out that progress in scientific knowledge has enabled improvements in human living conditions through myriads of technological innovations. They both seem to be good, and both are propagated incessantly today as such, but is this unmitigatedly so? Is there another side of the coin? An essential ambivalence? A darker underbelly?

From the very beginning of Western thinking with the Greeks, knowledge (ἐπιστήμη) has always been concerned with what was coming from the temporal dimension of the future, either by predicting it or, better, by positively shaping it. The former could be had via signs from the gods or through knowledge of the causes, whereas the latter was realized by means of the sedimentation of knowledge into the various arts of making (τέχναι ποιητικαί), which always involved also a knowledge of and skill with materials in order to bring forth what was envisaged as the telos. Here there is a will to power over movement and change at work that seems to be unadulteratedly good, beneficial for humankind and, moreover, has no in-built or inherent limit (there is always room for improvement, as they say). As unadulterated, unmitigated, untempered, unlimited, infinite (ἄπειρον), this Western will to shape the future may be called the absolute will to power over all kinds of movement and change. The bridling of the excesses of this will to power has been assigned to ethics which, in both Platonic and Aristotelean variants, have an appreciation of the dangers of the limitless. Unfortunately, traditional ethics as handed down from the Greeks, even to the present day, has no ontology of the specific kind of movement pertaining to sociative interplay* through which mortals could consider limits to their actions. The only kind of movement for which Greek thinking explicitly worked out an ontology is that of physical movement.

Greek thinking also concentrated upon the art of physically making things, to the exclusion of other arts, notably the art of acquisition (τέχνη κτητική) and the art of wealth-getting (τέχνη χρηματιστική). Aristotle does treat the latter briefly, pointing out its dangerous nature that resides in its inherent limitlessness; there is never an end to wealth-getting, whereas the art of acquisition may find an end in acquiring the desired use-value. Only millennia later, in the 19th century, was a Western philosopher, a meticulous student of Aristotle, able to convert Aristotle's insight into the limitless of wealth-getting into the famous formula for the essence of capital: M->C->M+ΔM, or money-capital advanced in order to get more money, a surplus value. This formula turns the formula for exchanging one use-value for another, i.e. C1->M->C2 upside down. With this inversion, as it turns out in our age, the world is also turned topsy-turvy. In the latter formula, money serves only as a means to an end, namely, that of acquiring a good on the market with another use-value, whereas in the formula for wealth-getting, the beginning and end of a circuit differ only quantitatively in amounts of money-capital. The circuit has no definite end-point, but can be repeated endlessly.

Marx deciphers these circuits. especially the former, as circuits of transformation of forms or 'sights' of thingified value. In my formulation, that takes Marx's thinking a step further, what capital is, i.e. its essence, is a limitlessly augmentative circuit of the Medium of thingified value. Limitless valorization of the Medium of thingified value is the law or principle of movement of what is commonly called capitalism. One could say that today's global capitalist economy is driven by the absolute will to valorize the Medium of thingified value. As absolute, the will is limitless, never coming to an end (τέλος) where it could be finally satiated.

The absolute will to power over all kinds of movement and change and the absolute will to valorize the Medium are interlinked and intimately intermeshed through the circumstance that improvements in the productivity of production and circulation processes, including the acceleration of turnover, enhance the valorization of the Medium. These two insatiable wills are personified by two hitherto unknown gods that subterraneanly inhabit our historically shared mortal mind. I name them Willy P. and Pleon Exia (lit.: more-having). Together, in a pernicious partnership, they exercise hidden hegemony over our mind, that is all the more effective for being hidden. For it seems superficially, through the fog of implicitness, that the principles of movement for which these unbridled gods stand are unreservedly good: improvement of the human condition through mastery of movement and change, coupled with enhanced material standards of living. In their ambivalence, they are impostors impersonating the Good and the Fair. And if they do not stand unqualifiedly for the Good (there are downsides), then — even without insight into the depth of our infection by these divinities, amounting to unabashed cluelessness — it appears (or rather: we kid ourselves) that their 'excesses' can be contained and regulated, say, through liberal-democratic government and a system of international organizations institutionalizing 'universal' human values. In this way, 'our Western' system of values, including above all individual freedom, may be preserved.

The adoration of Pleon Exia and Willy P. is performed unknowingly, but — under this veil of ignorance — all the more fervently. Among the rich and political elites, the fervour intensifies to a feverish frenzy masked by arrogant complacency.

* Cf. Social Ontology of Whoness Chapter 5 'Ontology of Exchange'.

Further reading: Tale of the Qua: A Philosophical Comedy

Social Ontology of Whoness: Rethinking Core Phenomena of Political Philosophy De Gruyter, Berlin 2018.

On Human Temporality: Recasting Whoness Da Capo De Gruyter, Berlin 2024.

Aristotle's purely energetic god of the fair

Capitalocene & The global law of movement.

23 May 2025

Mind over matter

In the physics of relativity theory, time is conceived as quantitative, being measured by the path taken by light through space, whether it be straight (special relativity) or curved (general relativity with gravitational curvature). Any physical event is then specified by four-dimensional space-time co-ordinates (x,y,z,ct) with the fourth spatialized time co-ordinate measuring the time taken for light (i.e. electromagnetic radiation) to travel from the event to an observer's signal receiver. Hence, for example, we on Earth are approximately 8 light-minutes from the Sun and 1 light-second from the Moon. This entails in particular that everything we perceive sensuously on Earth with our eyes is bathed in and made visible by light that is at least eight minutes old. It was emitted from fusion reactions in the Sun itself and made its way to Earth.

This is the way Einstein tailored his relativity theory to suit the needs of cosmological theory, whose empirical input consists of electromagnetic data received on Earth by any sort of receiver, including optical, radio or other kind of telescope. Cosmologists readily accept that they are, as they say, 'looking back in time' along the path of light taken by a cosmological event to the receiver.  Hence registered (clock-) time is relative to the observer-receiver.

For our mind, however, there is no (linear) time delay in thinking of the Sun as there is in receiving physical light from the Sun. We only ever see the Sun by eyesight with a delay of eight minutes, whereas we can think of the Sun instantaneously at any time, even at night when the Sun is sensuously invisible, and without employing any apparatus. Similarly, anything physical we perceive visually on Earth by daylight is perceived only in the present moment with the aid of eight-minute-old light from the Sun illuminating what is perceived. 

By contrast, my mind and your mind can think of and understand not only its sensuously perceptible environment, but also anything at all, both physical and non-physical, passed through to it from any of the temporal dimensions of past, present and future. The mind can move and switch freely from one imagined situation to another, skipping from one temporal dimension to another. Even the present, sensuously perceived situation is only understood by being interpreted by the mind with the help of the power of imagination. The openness of the three temporal dimensions for such mental skipping and interleaving of situations, both physically material and non-material, is entirely different from the measured, linear time not only of relativity physics, but of all physical science. Throughout modern science one is content with measuring time along the so-called time-line to pin-point events of all kinds, including  non-physical ones such as the handing down of a verdict by a court.

As I said, relativistic physics is dependent upon light to see anything at all, to register the data of anything physically material. The science of physics in general investigates the movement of anything physical that can be moved, with physical beings themselves being characterized as having extension and being composed of matter, matter itself having measurable mass. This is the way it has been with physics since its inception with the ancient Greeks, although the mathematization of physics only sets in with a vengeance much later, in the 17th century, thus turning extension (μέγεθος _megethos_) and mass (ὄγκος _onkos_) into quantitative mathematical variables.

The detection of physical events of extended, massive things by light, however, has the quirk that, according to both relativity theory and quantum theory, the light signal upon which such detection depends is composed of a stream of massless photons. Even more quirky is that in principle, according to Einstein's famous equation of mass-energy equivalence, E=m.c^2, physical mass can be converted entirely into the pure motion of massless light. The speed of light c is only attainable when all mass dissolves into pure motion. Light is therefore on the cusp of dissolution into the non-material altogether.

Modern science, however, is highly sceptical about there being anything at all non-material, and this prejudice is reinforced by modern physics, which claims to be the foundational science for all natural and social science. It has an intense focus (in particle physics) on the investigation of matter down to its smallest building blocks in quantum entities which are conceived as the fundamental particles from which all entities at all are 'made'. Quantum entities (including the Higgs boson) are then supposed to 'explain' the 'creation' of the entire universe, along linear time, of course, linking cause and effect. The beginning of all is then located at the beginning of the time-line called the Big Bang (or some other imagined mathematized theoretical construct).

Is that which truly exists, the famous ὄντως ὄν (_ontos on_) of Plato and the Platonists, in the end nothing ideal, but thoroughly material? Is it only matter that truly exists? Only material causes count throughout modern science because they enable material manipulation and hence the mastery of all kinds of movement and change of at least materially based entities. This mastery starts with being able to predict movement, to precalculate it. Taken literally and etymologically, the ὄντος ὄν can be translated as the 'beingly being' or the 'essentially essencing', with both 'being' and 'essencing' being understood participially as a kind of ongoing, continuous movement. Such essencing has to be entirely incomprehensible and foreign to modern science.

Again, is it the case as it seems to be under the hegemony of modern science and its lead science, physics that it is only matter that truly exists? Every phenomenon modern science attempts to grasp is led back to putative material causes, even the movement of the mind itself (in neuroscience). But what is matter? Matter is already an interpretation, i.e. an accomplishment of the mind. In today's modern physics, matter is a certain interpretation within our own historical epoch that differs from its interpretation in another historical age. In this sense, matter itself is an idea! This idea is an historical, hermeneutic cast of what matter is conceived to be in our age. One could object that this is circular thinking, and indeed it is. What matter itself 'truly is' can only be thought within an hermeneutic circle that is inextricably linked with the interpretations other primitive phenomena, notably, movement and time itself.

I have already pointed out that the physical movement of material beings is a special kind of movement amenable to being conceived along linear time, which itself is a specific, historical interpretation of time initiated by the Greeks, and Aristotle in particular. Such physical movement has been at the heart of Western science since its beginnings. Today, physical, material beings can be modelled by mathematized, or at least quantified, physical theories with an eye to mastering, i.e. predicting, their movement and change. 

As indicated above however, the movement of the non-physical mind is not subject to such physical restrictions. The mind moves freely through an entirely different kind of time that is no longer one-dimensional, but three-, or even four-dimensional (the fourth dimension allowing the passing-through of unified three-dimensional time to the psyche with its mental power of understanding; cf. On Human Temporality esp. Sections 1.2 and 2.2). The purest, freest kind of movement, that of the mind, is non-material*, although nothing prevents the mind from thinking of things material, without being affected by them. The mind can indeed follow physical movements along linear time as a special case, as it does in modern physics. But to interpret the movement of the mind itself, an alternative historical hermeneutic of time is required. Moreover, mental movement and physical movement do not exhaust the kinds of movement readily accessible and observable in familiar phenomena. Both social, sociating movement and economic movement, for instance, demand their own investigations of what these kinds of movement are.

* The embodied mind of us mortal humans does require the material brain as its organ, its tool, and mental movement can be impeded by dysfunctional bodily organs, but thinking itself is a non-material kind of movement.

Further reading:  On Human Temporality: Recasting Whoness Da Capo De Gruyter, Berlin 2024.

Three laws of movement (again).

12 May 2025

Liquid trees

It is hardly contentious that all modern science is materialist, including even psychology, that seems compelled to prove its scientific credentials by referring and reducing to neuronal processes. The social sciences, too, investigate the positive 'reality' of materially anchored, social practices and structures. But what is matter? Is it what can be perceived by the bodily senses and measured by various techniques and apparatuses to provide data for analysis? Is it what extended, physical beings are made of?

Already with the ancient Greeks, science (ἐπιστήμη _epistaemae_) focused on physical beings with size (μέγεθος _megethos_), extension (ἔκτασις _ektasis_)  and mass (ὄνκος _onkos_). Their word for matter is ὕλη (_hulae_), which in its everyday usage covers all sorts of wood: a forest of trees, timber for building, firewood fuel. For the Greeks, the paradigmatic kind of matter is tree, from which the philosophical concept of matter is abstracted, or 'pulled off'.

Modern physics and chemistry would seem to have come a long way from this primitive Greek conception of matter, but is this truly the case? Modern physics has broken down matter into sub-atomic entities including protons, neutrons, electrons, and even stranger entities such as quarks and gluons holding them together like glue, and light itself, composed of streams of massless quantum entities called photons (from Greek φῶς, _phos_ for 'light'). Light is the purest form of energy, consisting of massless photons travelling at maximum physical speed c, the speed of light, thus representing the purest form of transformation of matter into movement, as expressed in Einstein's famous equation E=m.c^2.

In the present globalized world, energy is of vital importance not just physically by powering the movement of all sorts of technological things in production processes, but prior to that, and even more so, in powering such technological things for the sake of keeping valorization of the Medium going, i.e. the endless circular movement of thingified value going through its various value-form transformations to generate surplus-value. The hidden global imperative is that thingified value endlessly augment.

Although the valorization movement of thingified value is purely formal and infinite, it also requires the physical movements of production and circulation, including the activity of human labour, for its endless augmentation. Only by virtue of valorization of the Medium being endless does it have also an endless need for physical energy to drive all the necessary physical movements, enhanced by various technologies for the sake of cost-cutting productivity increases that, in turn, enhance the generation of surplus value.

These technologies have long since liberated themselves from a reliance on matter in the Greek sense, i.e. on wood. Technological devices and buildings are no longer made merely of wood, and energy is no longer provided by burning firewood. We moderns flatter ourselves that we have long since surpassed what a Greek carpenter can do with timber or a Greek blacksmith can achieve with a hammer, anvil and a charcoal fire. We have moved on to more sophisticated fuels as energy sources such as coal, oil and natural gas. All these so-called fossil fuels, however, derive from decomposed trees extracted from the Earth's crust. Trees decompose over geological æons into solid coal, liquid oil and gaseous natural gas, and all three fossil fuels can be burnt to generate electric current that is today the preferred power source for any physical movement, especially as required by valorization of the Medium.

It is even the case that liquid trees, i.e. mineral oil, is the material employed to make myriad kinds of plastics that are ubiquitous in today's world. Without the discovery of polymers, many modern technologies would be impossible, and our lives as players in the gainful game would not be so convenient, environmental pollution by plastics be damned.

The depletion of the Earth's huge deposits of fossil fuels by digging them up or otherwise extracting them, then burning them, has led inevitably, over frighteningly few centuries, to devastation of the Earth for the sake of endless valorization. Climate change, with devastating ramifications, including geopolitically, is upon us. Political efforts are being undertaken to accomplish the momentous shift from fossil fuels to renewable energy sources for the sake of sustainability. But who is seriously asking: sustainability of what?

Further reading: Laws of movement & Energy.

'An Invisible Global Social Value' TT&S Vol. 5 no. 2, 2024.

Capitalocene & The global law of movement.

Sustainability? Of what?.

Three laws of movement (again).

06 May 2025

Three laws of movement (again)

Let us take another look at three laws of movement already addressed in other posts (see links below):


i) the second Newtonian law of physical motion 

f = m.a (or force is equal to mass times acceleration),

ii) Einstein's astounding law of mass-energy equivalence 

E = m.c^2
(energy is equal to mass times the speed of light squared), 

and

iii) Marx's basic formula for the valorization of thingified value as capital 

M -> C -> M+ΔM
(value-form transformation of advanced money-capital into commodities required for a production process and the further value-transformation of the product via the circulation process into money-capital returned with a surplus value).

Re i): Newton's classical second law of motion is a most elegant example of how the physical motion of a physical body, regarded as a point mass, can be encapsulated in a surprisingly simple mathematical equation. The scope of its application seemed for centuries to be unlimited, albeit that its first realm of application, in the 17th century, was that of planetary motion, which was at the focus of attention for great names such as Kepler, Galileo and Newton. Along with the law of inertia and of equal and opposite reaction between interacting physical bodies, the law was cast as applying throughout the universe in an homogeneous mathematized (real vector) space ticking uniformly with an absolute, continuous, real time variable t.

Galileo's famous dictum of 1623 in his Il Saggiatore that the laws of nature are written in the language of mathematics nevertheless turns the truth upside down. Rather, it is the absolute will to power over all kinds of movement that dictates, in particular, that the physical (loco)motion of (celestial) bodies be made precalculable through an appropriate kind of mathematics, namely, the infiinitesimal calculus. Mathematical precalculable predictability of movement satisfies the will to power over movement by reducing physical motion to solvable equations. 

Already a century earlier, in 1543, with his book De revolutionibus orbium coelestium, Copernicus had ostensibly empirically proved that the Sun does not revolve around the Earth, but conversely the Earth around the Sun. This is nonsense, of course, because motion is relative and reciprocal: if, from A's standpoint, B revolves around it, then conversely, from B's standpoint, A revolves around B. The point of Copernicus' discovery is that the motion of the planets becomes mathematically more elegantly describable from the perspective of the Sun's reference frame as revolutions around the Sun. The complications of Ptolemaic epicycles of planets revolving around the Earth are done away with, paving the way for a more uniform, elegant Newtonian theory of gravitational motion in an homogeneous space.

Re ii): Einstein's mind-boggling equation E = m.c^2 pronounces the equivalence of mass and energy as a postulate of special relativity theory. It was derived not by considering the equivalent of Newton's second law, but by considering and postulating the equivalent of the classical principle of conservation of momentum. Whereas in Newtonian mechanics, a) (counted clock-) time is taken to be uniform throughout the universe and b) the mass of a physical body is taken to be a non-transformable constant in physical interactions, in Einsteinian special relativity, a) (counted clock-) time is relative to the observer's inertial frame of reference and b) mass depends on the body's speed in a given reference frame. The momentum of a physical particle no longer depends solely on its velocity, but also upon its relativistically variable mass. This circumstance links mass with physical movement and thus with kinetic energy. Time itself becomes the one-dimensional path of light, that is linked to the three spatial dimensions via the Lorentz transformation. Henceforth, physical events are conceived as happening in the universe at space-time co-ordinates (x,y,z.ct) in an observer's frame of reference. (The observer here may be simply an apparatus set up somewhere to gather physical data.)

As a body (particle) approaches the speed of light in a given inertial reference frame, its mass tends toward infinity, at least according to the equation expressing the relativistic mass in terms of a particle's rest mass. In other words, the greater the momentum and kinetic energy of a particle, the greater its mass and, in the limit, the threatened, physically impossible infinitude of mass is averted by the conversion of all the mass into the motion of pure light composed of a stream of massless, quantized photons. Matter dissolves into (divine?) light. Einstein's equation expresses nothing other than this possibility of the transformation of matter into pure, energetic movement (including the thermal energy of atoms and molecules in motion) — the physical law for developing nuclear energy and atomic bombs. Anything physical moving at the speed of light cannot have any mass, which is the case for electromagnetic radiation. Note that, whereas the absolute speed limit for anything physical is equal to c, this speed limit does not apply to the movement of the mind, which is non-spatial and hence both nowhere and everywhere.

Note also that, whereas Newtonian gravitational force only acts upon physical bodies with mass, in general relativity theory massless light is subject to gravitational force by dint of its being equivalent to the curvature of space-time itself. The straight path of light in special relativity becomes its curved path in general relativity.

Re iii): Marx's formula for the valorization movement of (the Medium of) thingified value has hitherto not been called a law of movement. Unlike Newton's and Einstein's laws, it is non-predicative but instead enunciates an inexorable principle that the transformational circuiting of advanced capital through its value-forms must fulfil if the circuit is to be sustainable. If a circuit of valorization does not generate a surplus, but instead a loss diminishing the originally advanced money-capital, this endangers the movement altogether, because eventually the capital will consume itself and end up as nothing. 

The law of movement usually associated with Marx's Das Kapital read in the orthodox way is the so-called labour theory of value that Marx adopted in a modified form from Adam Smith. But this 'law of labour-value' is untenable; equal amounts of embodied "socially necessary labour-time" do not change hands in the exchange of commodity goods and services (nor even a regulated modification of such labour-time quantities as investigated in the so-called 'transformation problem'). Rather, quite the opposite: it is the exchange itself in the Medium of thingified value that determines the magnitude of a commodity's value. The commodity's embodied labour is thus evaluated on the market itself.

The deeper insight offered by Marx's main work is that a capitalist economy, and especially a global capitalist economy, must satisfy the principle of valorization if it is to remain viable. This is the law that rules the global economy. Hence economic growth must be unlimited, the finiteness of the Earth and all that lives on it be damned. This law of movement remains invisible and unknown to the modern science of economics because this social science is lacking its foundational concepts. They can only be uncovered by thinking socio-ontologically. The Medium of thingified value, namely, is an ontological form (εἶδος or 'look') of sociated labour that remains invisible to empiricist thinking.

The valorization of thingified value is plainly not a physical movement as such, but a principle governing the sociation in a capitalist economy. It does require, however, also kinds of physical movement associated with the production and circulation processes. Commodity goods and services have to be produced by many different kinds of labour employing many different kinds of physical means of production. Similarly, such produced commodity goods and services have to be actually sold to realize sales revenues for the capitalist enterprise, and this requires labour, including that of transportation and marketing, again employing the appropriate physical means. This entails in particular that the productivity of a production process can be measured via appropriate physical quantities such as hourly physical output which, in turn, can be converted into a measure of labour productivity if wage-costs are known. Each unit output then costs x cents in labour costs, but what the product can be sold for on the market is a brute fact that may have little connection with the labour costs.

As I said, the movement of valorization cannot be seen as such without the appropriate socio-ontological concepts. What capitalism is essentially, i.e. its ontological whatness, remains today an unposed and unanswered question. The social science of economics therefore cannot come to grips with the truth of this kind of sociating movement and instead fudges the questions, engaging wilfully in obfuscation. In remaining blind to the truth, economic movements are then (merely) explained by empirically based theoretical models. Economists look at empirical regularities and patterns from the past and try to extrapolate them more or less successfully. They tend to use sentences starting with 'History tells us that ...'. There is no unified economic theory at all, but only various bits and pieces of theoretical explanation for various scenarios based on unending empirical research. Empiricist modern social science does not even notice the deficit.

Further reading: Newton mathematizes Aristotelean ontology.

Laws of movement & Energy.

'An Invisible Global Social Value' TT&S Vol. 5 no. 2, 2024.

Capitalocene & The global law of movement.

Sustainability? Of what?

Appendix: 'A demathematizing phenomenological interpretation of quantum-mechanical indeterminacy' in Movement and Time in the Cyberworld De Gruyter, Berlin 2019.

Social Ontology of Whoness: Rethinking Core Phenomena of Political Philosophy De Gruyter, Berlin 2018.

On Human Temporality: Recasting Whoness Da Capo De Gruyter, Berlin 2024.